Abandonment: Notes on the Thought of Jean-Luc Nancy

by | 27 Mar 2013

KEY CONCEPT

Fernand Léger 1942 Dance

In his distinctive concern for etymology, Nancy notes that abandonment contains the semantic unit bandon, which is ‘an order, a prescription, a decree, a permission, and the power that holds these freely at its disposal.’ (Nancy 1993, 44) A ban in this context should be understood as a general proclamation of the sovereign rather than specific prohibition. To abandon, therefore, is to be delivered over to the sovereign ban and, as such, one always abandons to a law.

What does such a law prescribe? Nothing but abandonment. Both law and abandonment are conceived ontologically, where ‘abandonment remains the sole predicament of being.’ (Ibid 36) Given the multiple ways of thinking and speaking being, abandoned being is abandonment to the very possibility of such multiplicity, to the law of existence that opens on to the world in its efflorescence. At the same time, abandonment implies the exhaustion of transcendentals, the terminal insufficiency of any constructed sense of originary being. As such, the being of human being is in abandonment to the extent that it enters a forgetful oblivion, ‘to be abandoned it to be left with nothing to keep hold of and no calculation.’ (Ibid 39)

Being abandoned to the entirety of law means abandonment cannot lose respect for law. This is not a forced respect. This is how it is, ‘“it cannot do otherwise” means it cannot be otherwise.’ (Ibid 44)

The idea of respect, from respicere, literally means to look back. Abandonment is therefore the glance, regard or better still, the consideration towards what comes before abandonment, that is to say, the considered relation to law in its totality. To lose respect for law would be to lose the very relation that is its sense, ‘by respecting the law, abandonment respects itself, so to speak (and the law respects it).’ (Ibid 45)

If the law commands nothing but abandonment, then this can now be more precisely articulated as the command to see or behold being in its abandonment. This is so in spite of the impossibility of containing being within a partial vision. Being, to this extent, remains invisible. Yet being is still there (the ‘y’ of il y a), which means being is also here and the ‘[here] opens a spacing, clears an area upon which being is thrown, abandoned.’ (Ibid 47)

Abandonment is thus the inaugural throwing of being, from the very birth of being, and there is nothing upon which abandoned being relies, which makes it non-dialectical, and nothing to which abandoned being can go back to, which renders being in a permanent state of being born. (Ibid 37)

Abandonment is the dereliction of being or the forsaking of being, which enables us to speak in general terms of autonomy, freedom and the possibility of thinking.

Postscript

Jean-Luc Nancy’s analysis of abandonment contains ideas that I anticipate many will consider not only very difficult but also problematic, in particular, the idea that abandonment cannot lose respect for law. If we are beholden to law in our very being, does this mean it is impossible to be outside the law — an outlaw? Are there no more rebels? What about the very important political act of disobedience? If you were wondering this then you can count on Giorgio Agamben for company, who writes with reference to Nancy that ‘[o]nly if it is possibile to think the Being of abandonment beyond every idea of law … will we have moved out of the paradox of sovereignty toward a politics freed from every ban.’ (Agamben 59) On this account, Nancy does not seem to offer much for critical legal theory, especially that branch of it that is interested in thinking outside or against the law.

But let’s not be too quick to dismiss him. To appreciate better what is happening here we need to further understand his analysis of Kant’s intimate association of law with freedom (see esp. Nancy 2003, 133ff). We need to understand how, as a consequence, the law of freedom becomes the law of the law and, in its radical emptiness, the law without law or the law that does not cease freeing itself from law. We are then left with a radiant paradox: the law guarantees the outlaw, it guarantees the exception to the exception, indeed it becomes their condition of possibility.

References

—Agamben, Giorgio. 1998. Homo Sacer, Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
—Nancy, Jean-Luc. 1993. The Birth to Presence. Trans. Brian Holmes & Others. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Nancy, Jean-Luc 2003. A Finite Thinking. Ed. Simon Sparks. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

2 Comments

    • Thanks for these pieces Gil. And a great final para. about freedom (a free law) being that which requires the ordered law as that from which it liberates itself.

      There is a thing in Seneca I think where he says that if the most powerful things (the gods) free themselves from the order of the world, they free themselves absolutely – that is, they turn their backs and become indifferent.

      Reply

Submit a Comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.

POSTS BY EMAIL

Join 4,662 other subscribers

We respect your privacy.

FAIR ACCESS PUBLISHER
IN LAW AND THE HUMANITIES

Fair access = access according to ability to pay
on a sliding scale down to zero.

JUST PUBLISHED: VIRAL CRITIQUE

PUBLISH ON CLT

Publish your article with us and get read by the largest community of critical legal scholars, with over 4000 subscribers.